There exist two competing tendencies in modern society: individualism, and specialization. These can be understood as two elements to an overall trend toward atomization. Nevertheless, the first asks us to avoid being dependent on others while the second makes dependence practically necessary.
Products which offer increased independence are marketable in this environment. Tools which offer to simplify your life are one example, and the most predominant, but others are possible.
Consider the automobile: it was first made popular as a symbol of independence and freedom. The car has now lost much of that aura. It may be there for some, particularly teenagers, and it does offer the same increased mobility as ever, but it has become commonplace. Imagine, then, simplifying the aspect of life related to owning a car. What would this look like? IKEA cars--cars built for home maintenance. Constructing the car so that all of its components are as easily accessible as possible, and as resilient as feasible.
Would this sell? Probably. Would it be profitable? I think it could be, if done right. each component should be made as independent of other components as possible, and should be sold to the common car owner. Instead of designing a new car each year, the manufacturer may then produce upgraded versions of the various components. A car owner may then buy a single component, or a whole new car, or anything in between, as he can afford. I suspect, done right, some people would spend more on car parts than they now do (keeping in mind that they should not have to spend much, if anything, on man-hours to install those parts), thus making more money for the manufacturer.
This could also speed the acceptance of electric cars if the car were built as an electrical car. This would make sense, because that would reduce the number of fluids that would need to be moved around the whole vehicle. The challenges which generally face electric cars would remain, but the benefits of not needing to spend as much money (and unusable car-hours) on maintaining the car could help overcome those.
Thursday, May 28, 2015
Self-maintenance: The Future of Car-repair?
Saturday, May 23, 2015
Sartre and Meaning in the World
Sartre assumes the lack of God, and takes this to entail a lack of meaning to the world a priori. That is, to Sartre, if there is no God to determine the meaning of things--the mattering of things to persons--then it is up to whatever mind there is to determine how things matter.
The dependency of meaning on mind is right. To matter, a thing must matter to something. That meaning is undetermined apart from a prior mind setting the meaning seems, to me, to be wrong. To set the meaning of words involves a cultural use of the words in a certain way, and this is a case where meaning is set by minds in a wholly contingent way. On the other hand, that breaking my leg is painful is given by the facts of how the world is and how I am, and it is such that the relevant aspects of my makeup are not (easily) available for me to change. Thus, the meaning of a broken leg as bad is given by how things are, independently of the choices of minds.
Where God exists, he may set the meaning of things by setting how the world is. He creates a material world with meaning to us by creating it and us in a particular way. The matter of creation coheres, in this case, with the will and command of God.
Sartre's view of how things mean is dominant in today's society. The idea that an action may mean "nothing" depends, in many cases, on the assumption that the human will is in charge of the meaning of things, of bodily actions. The thought that music or sex might not be taken seriously as meaning what they appear to mean, or have historically meant, depends on this view.
An alternative materialist view would be one which said that where only matter exists, the structure of matter is what determines the meaning of life. This would make the meaning of certain bodily actions (sex, cutting, drugs and alcohol, etc.,) dependent upon how those actions affected one and those around one.
The Sartrean view holds, also, that we are ultimately free. That is, that we may do whatever it is we choose to do. This does not mean we can fly, but that we may seek any aim we will. It is not a denial of the material structure of the world's impingement on what and how we can act, but a denial of the idea that we are constrained by our character or upbringing. It is a denial of the fittingness of allowing a pre-existing culture to impact one's own behaviors. Sartre was hipster before it was cool.
The dependency of meaning on mind is right. To matter, a thing must matter to something. That meaning is undetermined apart from a prior mind setting the meaning seems, to me, to be wrong. To set the meaning of words involves a cultural use of the words in a certain way, and this is a case where meaning is set by minds in a wholly contingent way. On the other hand, that breaking my leg is painful is given by the facts of how the world is and how I am, and it is such that the relevant aspects of my makeup are not (easily) available for me to change. Thus, the meaning of a broken leg as bad is given by how things are, independently of the choices of minds.
Where God exists, he may set the meaning of things by setting how the world is. He creates a material world with meaning to us by creating it and us in a particular way. The matter of creation coheres, in this case, with the will and command of God.
Sartre's view of how things mean is dominant in today's society. The idea that an action may mean "nothing" depends, in many cases, on the assumption that the human will is in charge of the meaning of things, of bodily actions. The thought that music or sex might not be taken seriously as meaning what they appear to mean, or have historically meant, depends on this view.
An alternative materialist view would be one which said that where only matter exists, the structure of matter is what determines the meaning of life. This would make the meaning of certain bodily actions (sex, cutting, drugs and alcohol, etc.,) dependent upon how those actions affected one and those around one.
The Sartrean view holds, also, that we are ultimately free. That is, that we may do whatever it is we choose to do. This does not mean we can fly, but that we may seek any aim we will. It is not a denial of the material structure of the world's impingement on what and how we can act, but a denial of the idea that we are constrained by our character or upbringing. It is a denial of the fittingness of allowing a pre-existing culture to impact one's own behaviors. Sartre was hipster before it was cool.
Wednesday, May 20, 2015
The Meaning of the World
The human being is a primarily embodied, acting body. The
human qua agent does things, and most of these things are bodily actions. We
can most easily, then, approach an understanding of the human being from the
point of view of bodily action. We can discover through this some elements of
mental action, namely, purpose. This will lead us to concept and psyche
formation. The aim, here, is to develop an understanding of how an infant might
come to comprehend the world in a mostly empirical way.
First, bodily action: our bodies move, for some purpose. To
count as an action, rather than a mere behavior, a mere bodily event, the
bodily movement must be motivated. There must be an acceptance on the part of
the one whose body it is that the “Why?” question has application. Thus, an
action is a behavior for the sake of a purpose. The purpose might itself be an
action. I may be digging a hole in order to unbury treasure, I might be lifting
weights in order to get stronger in order to have an easier time carrying furniture
up stairs, I might be cleaning in order to be a good husband, and so on.
Action, then, has in its nature the means-end relation. To
phi as an action is always to phi for the sake of psi-ing, where psi-ing is
also an action. Of course, these relations cannot go on forever. Some action or
actions must be deemed to-be-done simply, without reference to some additional
action or characterization of the action for which sake it is done. This
requires that some action or actions be, by their very nature, to-be-done. For
an action to simply be to-be-done requires that it follow from the nature of
the agent that the agent should, to be a good one of its kind, do that action,
that is, the action which is to-be-done simply for an agent is to be a good
kind of the thing one is.
Our conception of the kind of thing we are, then, will
naturally give rise to action. It sets the purpose of a being. Here we arrive
at the question of how we form our conception of ourselves. I do not mean,
here, to suppose that we do this intentionally, or even consciously. Rather, I
take it that there is something from which and for the sake of which we act and
that it could be construed as our beliefs, whether conscious or not, as to the
kind of thing we are. This will also have to do with how our nature relates to
the world. Let us call those elements of our action-generating concept which
vary from situation to situation our concept of our situation. Within any given
circumstance we will act on the basis of what we think we are capable of. This
is our concept of ourselves. Our situations are usually defined with respect to
ourselves.
Each action has
consequences in the world and (often thereby) ourselves. We learn what
precisely are the consequences of which actions over time, by experiencing the
consequences multiple times. We learn how the world is by finding what we can
do in relation to the world. Our concept of a tree begins when a tree’s
existence has consequences for our actions. The discovery of the world is the
discovery of what the world means for us, and how we can alter how the world
is. The world is, then, in a sense, a text which we can edit. By editing this
text, we discover the meaning of the world. Acting is, at an early stage, much
like scribbling lines on paper and going, “Mommy, what does this say?” Very
often, we might say, the meaning of an action is what it does in the world.
To understand the world is to understand what one should do,
given certain ends. To say that ethics is objective is to say that there are things
which everyone should do whatever their ends. To claim that everyone ought to
do such-and-such whatever their other ends requires one of two things: either
that any end an agent might hold require the doing of such-and-such, or that
whatever end an agent holds, their wellbeing is bound up with doing
such-and-such. These two are very similar, since people believe that what they
are doing is contributive to their wellbeing. To show that something is
necessary to the wellbeing of a person is to show that they should do it.
***
The seeking of the good for oneself involves a kind of
hermeneutical circle. I enter the question of what is good with certain
preconceptions, which I have gathered from my upbringing, my environment, and
whatever other factors there may be. I presume that this is good for me. I then do the sorts of things I expect to be
good. Movement happens when I find that this way of living is not conducive to
my wellbeing. I find that living this way results in certain things which I
take to be bad, rather than good. Thus, I find my view of what is conducive to
my wellbeing to be inconsistent, and therefore requiring change.
The world, including my own body restricts plausible views
of what is good by failing to present certain things in response to certain
actions. To view smoking as good is possible, but requires viewing the benefits
of smoking here and now as more important than the later benefits of avoiding
smoking. One cannot view long life and smoking as both good without some story
of why they do not fit together in most lives. Likewise, certain kinds of
people may find the goods of social or intellectual life to drain or energize
them more than others, and this will have consequences for what they find to be
good for them.
This provides space for the right thing to do to vary
depending on bodily makeup. Those with sensitive hearing may find that they
should avoid loud music. Those who are hard of hearing find themselves in a
quite different position. Those with disabilities finds themselves in this sort
of situation with respect to whatever way they are disabled, and require
different things for their good than others might. Just as we allow individuals
to opt-out of activities that violate their religious convictions, we need to
enable those embodied differently to be able to live in the way they need,
since the moral demands on them are the same, albeit more empirically
verifiably. Those who need to phi in order to reduce stress ought, all else
being equal, to phi. Altering environments to be sensitive to varying sensory
needs takes priority over altering sensory needs because the body imposes needs
for all of us, because we depend on our bodily existence, and because it must
be possible for the individual to live prior to alterations given that those
alterations have not always existed. The environments which are problematic are
newer than the sensory needs, and so violate the living spaces of those who,
due to their bodily makeup, cannot function with them. Further, society ought
to focus on enabling living in more conditions, rather than primarily trying to
eliminate those conditions.
***
The problem of fitting disparate goods together is answered
by a Christian ethics which attends to both the fallen present and the
eschatological fulfillment. Why do the wicked benefit so often? Because the
world is fallen. Why not say that what is good changed with the fall? There
will be justice. Everything will be made right. Why bother doing good when we
will suffer for it? Because your reward will be great in heaven. Why do we
suffer for doing good? Because the world is fallen. No ethic devoid of this
kind of picture of what is wrong with the world and what is to come can
motivate and explain suffering for what is good.
This comes into play in the inward-turning ethics of
hedonism, stoicism, and skepticism. Each refuses to legitimate suffering for
good. The first makes the goal the avoidance of suffering by means of finding
balance in things. It is the philosophy of dieting, of working hard for good,
but not so hard it hurts. The second refuses to be affected by the external
world. What is outside of the agent’s control is not permitted to hurt him,
because happiness must be achievable, and it cannot be guaranteed when the
external world might foul it up. This is a refusal of the current fallen state
of the world, and a rejection of the need for it to be renewed. It is an utter
allegiance to the sovereign self who must be able to be happy in and of himself
(which is, again, the goal). The last, again, aims at happiness by not
affirming anything, but holding everything with an open hand. Not even beliefs
are permitted to taint the self with the fall. Each of these three philosophies
aims at a happiness unharmed by how things actually are, increasingly trying to
extricate the self from the effects of the fall. Each thereby denies the need
for salvation and the renewal of all things. By denying the need for renewal,
they give up any possibility for eschatological hope. Only an eschatological
hope allows us to suffer for the good. All others require that we assume that
if we are suffering, then we are not doing what is good.
It is true that a firm belief in the goodness of what one is
doing supports a kind of joy, but I do not think it is a joy that excludes
suffering, but, rather, we as Christians can rejoice in our sufferings because
we are sharing in the sufferings of Christ. We can affirm suffering as true
suffering because we can recognize it as a result of the fall, as to be
swallowed up in victory in the last days. We can say “For I consider that the
sufferings of this present time are not worth comparing with the glory that is
to be revealed to us.” (Romans 8:18). We recognize that we are living according
to the rules of a different world, but we live in this world as pilgrims. Our
citizenship is in heaven, not here on earth in this present age.
How can I claim that we find what is good through action in
the world, yet also say that, as Christians, we act according to the rules of a
different world? It is because this world is fallen, and is being renewed. It
is because this world still bears the marks of how it was made, and “will be
set free from its bondage to decay and obtain the freedom of the glory of the
children of God” (Romans 8:21). We live according to how God created the world,
and so agree with God as to how the world should be by living according to the
rules the world should present.
We claim that death is bad, and yet death surrounds us.
Without an eschatology which held out to us the bodily resurrection of the
dead, we would have to claim that the end of the body was to be accepted. It is
only in light of the resurrection that we can fully proclaim that death is bad,
and it is in light of the resurrection that death loses its sting. That death
is bad in the present points to the glory of the resurrection. That there is a
bodily resurrection vindicates our claim that death is bad for us. Because
death is bad, it must be overcome in Christ Jesus. Because it is overcome, we
need not fear it, but may live in the hope of eternal life in Jesus Christ our
Lord and Savior.
We live according to a view of our wellbeing which we can
live according to. If we require, as part of our view of human wellbeing, the
view that it is good for human bodily life to go on as long as possible, then
we are required to explain why it does not, and why we may not accept the end
as given. Why, if ongoing life is good, do people die? Why, if people do die,
should we be sad about that? The bodily resurrection of the dead, and the curse
of death which accompanied the fall, answers
these questions in the only way I
know.
This is the kind of thinking we are required to do in
putting together a view of what is good for human beings. It is the
interpretation of the world as a text, asking of each event how it fits into
the whole, and of the whole, how it stands in light of the parts. We ask what
we ought to desire if we are consistent in our values, and we ask whether those
values are thereby evidenced in the whole. We ask what we would do best to
value given our view of the whole, and we ask how we should then respond to
parts in light of the whole. Each part demands a response, but what response we
give depends on how we expect the whole of the world, unto eternity, to turn
out. The parts have their value in the way they do, but this may be vindicated
or refuted by how things turn out. Wealth, in and of itself, is good, but
wealth by theft ends poorly.
Everyone, then, has a practical eschatology. Everyone has
expectations of how the world will turn out, and they act according to these
expectations. Eschatology is not unique to those of us who believe we have been
told how it ends. People who live according to beliefs that history must turn
out this way or that also hold an eschatology. Even those who hold a
naturalistic view of things live according to how they expect things to turn
out because how things turn out affects what the best thing for them to do now
is. Our expectations are what we live toward. The Christian eschaton is the
foremost expectation in the Christian’s mind. The direction of history, or
stock market projections, or political predictions, or what-have-you are all
expectations which people live toward, however: in fear, in anticipation, in
hope. These drive action toward them, or, when it is “here is where things are
headed if we don’t do something” in revolt against them. But our hope is higher
and far more secure, and it drives us—If we understand and believe it—to act
unto the glory of God in love for others.
***
Not long ago, people were talking about “what’s wrong with
the ‘right/wrong side of history’ argument,” but what I hope is evident now is
that the argument is not always fallacious. It is no more fallacious than appealing
to a virtue term to appraise an action. The problem with the argument as it is
often used is that there is disagreement over how history ends, just as there
is sometimes difficulty using virtue terms when we disagree about what the
terms mean. Where there is agreement over how history ends, the argument is
valid. We all live toward how we expect history to end, and so pointing us to
that expectation is a perfectly reasonable way to motivate us to live according
to it. This is exactly what the passages dealing with the end times are there
for! The Bible uses, without apology, the right side of history argument, it
just looks to the very end of history, rather than the things in between which
will pass away with the rest of the current order of things when that day
comes.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)